Started 7 June 1999
Last changed
8th Sept. 2024 ............... Length about 7,500 words (51,000 bytes).
This is a WWW document maintained by Steve Draper, installed at http://www.psy.gla.ac.uk/~steve/reflection.html.
You may copy it. How to refer to it.
Web site logical path:
[www.psy.gla.ac.uk]
[~steve]
[this page]
Notes by
Stephen W. Draper
Department of Psychology
University of Glasgow
Glasgow G12 8QQ U.K.
email: steve@psy.gla.ac.uk
WWW URL: http://www.psy.gla.ac.uk/~steve/
Kurt Lewin: do it and learn from (thinking about) the experience.
These began as personal notes on the concept of "reflection" in learning and
education; taken from my notes on the Laurillard model of the learning and
teaching process. Basically, I have found many different senses of the concept,
and these notes try to enumerate those senses.
Triggered by the seminar conducted by
John Cowan at
TLS at
Glasgow University
on 10 Nov 1998 I revised and expanded the notes. There then followed an
email discussion, and that has led to me revising these notes further.
The main messages are:
- There are several meanings or usages of the word "reflection", even in the
educational literature, and these are unreconciled — not even properly
acknowledged, in fact.
- I offer a description of the range of meanings in terms of 4 dimensions.
- It seems to me that reflection as a concept or issue is of only
secondary importance: a component of more complete theories and approaches.
There are, however, really three issues involved here:
- Theories: The status of "reflection" in theories of learning and teaching
- Practice: Practical activities for learners designed around reflection
- Communication: The problem in communication about reflection, given the fact that
different authors mean different things, different from each other and
different from any meaning given in dictionaries; but most do not define what
they mean nor acknowledge that others mean something else.
[Triggered by the
Ray McAleese talk at SRHE'95]
- Nearest sense in a dictionary "Conscious thought; meditation".
Oxford English Dictionary: "Reflect: go back in thought, meditate or
consult with oneself."
- An argument with oneself = internalised Laurillard dialogue.
An interesting question here is whether there is an important contrast between
argument, dialogue, and cross-examination. Two themes here being detecting
and addressing inconsistencies, and trial and error — that is, producing
an action or opinion and then criticising it.
Re-expression, but it can be done as well as by oneself, so no teacher needed.
E.g. draw concept maps
E.g. draw argument structures. Cf. High Perry score, considering the
relationships betweeen evidence and several theories.
=> sorting out relationships (among concepts?) by externalisation
But this is purely at the conceptual level: about relationships between
concepts, not experiences.
- Laurillard uses it for the steps (by either teacher or learner) of going
from experience to concepts to modify the latter. (She uses "adaptation" for
modifying action by considering concepts.)
So concept maps i.e. processing the relationships between concepts would not
count.
* Kolb uses it essentially in this way.
- Reflection = self-awareness. I.e. reflexive thinking. True of experiential
learning if by self we mean what happened to the self and what it did. Cf.
also Suchman, and using plans to describe post hoc what/why you did.
- The maintainence of a mental image in consciousness to the exclusion of
competing ones = success of one pattern of activation over all others.
I.e. reflecting one view of the world in the mind. This is a use of
"reflection" consistent with the (false) theory that thinking is
representation, and representation is mirroring the world in the mind (cf.
Rorty). I.e. "reflection" could refer to that subset of thought that is
correctly described by those theories of mind and thought.
- Reflect as in a mirror; redescribe; use a new metaphor, a new concept to
concept connections. E.g. "Reflecting on the idea I heard today". This sounds
like (4), but here the mirror is not the mind, but a metaphor got from someone
else, or from brainstorming. So it is another technique belonging under (1).
- Any kind of processing after the fact; slightly delayed processing of
recent events; cf. my theory of stories. If any re-processing by the learner
is reflection then it refers to most of the 6 learner activities (4 of them).
- Schön reflection: thought about action (results),
which may change either action or knowledge. (Reflection in action,
reflection on action; knowledge in action, knowledge of action.) I.e. he
only applies it to the effects of action. Note too that his main stance is
against "technical rationality", but that the Laurillard model tacitly
embodies it by having the two level split of concepts and personal action.
Schön's point is that you can reflect on and modify action without
consulting theory. So Schön's reflection is actually in the iteration
within the level of personal experience, and NOT between the levels.
8.2 Note that for Schön, reflection is about modifying action; and doing
so with thinking but without the level of concepts. This is exactly the
opposite of Laurillard, who uses it only for modifying concepts.
- In education in general, a big concern is to get learners to relate action
and concepts. Probably the biggest part of that is from concepts to action
i.e. to change the way learners think and act in the world to be consistent
with the concepts they have learned.
9.2 For Schön, reflection uses observations (of effects of action?) to
drive reflection. But in my view in education the main effect you want is to
go from a new concept to its implications. A big such concern is to connect
with your own action; but perhaps even more, is to think through its
relationships with other ideas you have (consistency).
9.3 I would call this "reflection": it is certainly thinking, and not acting,
not just going ahead with routine exams and exercises. And it starts from
(new) concepts. This is the opposite of both Schön and Laurillard. It is
a kind of iteration within the conceptual level; but it is not the Laurillard
iteration of just re-expressing it. It is about working out connections and
relationships, and may also be relationships to action and personal
experience.
- Dewey is said to have "synonimised", i.e. argued that these are all
different words for a single activity): reflective thinking, reflective
judgment, problem solving, critical thinking. Dewey,J.(1933) How we
think (New York: Heath). And a key attribute of his view of this
thinking is that it is associated with problems with real uncertainty.
So perhaps the common theme is reflect = do more thinking about
something (7), making more connections in the mind (or more original
inferences); and perhaps actually inferring some new and useful aspect. Output
could be two kinds of thing: concepts and plans of action. Two major types of
subject for reflection: reflecting about sensorimotor experience, and
reflecting about verbal descriptions and concepts.
Hence note that (3) and (4) are mutually consistent, but inconsistent with (2).
There are in fact two rather different kinds of connection that we want to
prompt learners to make: a) with other concepts and facts they know (2); b)
with their own concrete experiences (3,4). These are different things,
probably requiring different techniques. Using concept maps is not promoting
reflection in the sense of making connections to personal experience. More
concretely, they are probably good revision tools, but not the thing for
getting students to connect the lab work with the lectures.
In the end, perhaps there are 3 levels of meaning for "reflect" in this
educational context:
- Think (more). I expand the kinds of thinking desirable in a learner in the next section.
- Iteration: a notion of going back and forth between thinking and
experience, between action and analysing its effects, or anyway between
thinking and something else that may give new material for thinking.
- Specifically working to relate theory and practice: public concepts and
personal experience.
The only common idea is more processing about something (6,7). It is about
thinking, not actual action; and strongly implies no time pressure, but
seeking understanding. It also implies no method, but a form of thinking to
see what emerges i.e. not strongly goal directed to arrive at a particular end,
but rather bottom up driven as a response to an internal estimate of unfinished
thinking business.
Currently, I think the varieties of reflection may be spanned using four
independent dimensions, some with subdimensions; and almost every combination
of alternatives makes sense.
It seems there are two distinct root meanings, each important to some
writers on the topic:
- A) extra thinking about material (about the subject domain)
already in the mind (reflection as meditation, reprocessing, re-examination)
- B) thinking about
oneself in order to achieve more conscious knowledge and control of oneself and
one's actions (reflection as reflexive: turned back in on oneself;
metacognition).
Thinking
about one's own actions bridges both aspects, because one's actions are one
important part of one's mental content, and because (better) control of oneself
means (better) control of one's actions.
The first basic meaning (A) of "reflection" is to think about something, but to
think internally: to brood on stuff already in your mind, not on new incoming
material (not new concepts, but revising what you already have some part of;
not new data, but new processing of already existing memories or plans for
action). One might take it to be an argument with oneself, an internal
dialogue as opposed to an interaction with a teacher, a peer, or with part of
the external world. As a cognitive function, it might be taken to be about
doing maintainence work on internal consistency: checking material against all
other material in the mind to detect and attempt to resolve any
contradictions.
Given that, then the key questions are
(1) on what material is the thinking done, and (2) when is it done.
The first question can be refined: the essence of (type A)
reflection is to review or create new connections, so the "on what" question
becomes: making connections from what to what? So 3 questions:
- What is reflected upon with a view to
changing it (e.g. actions, concepts, ...). Kolb and Laurillard reserve the
word "reflection" for thinking about and modifying concepts (in the light of
experience of action). Laurillard's model however is deeply symmetric, and
she uses the term "adaptation" for thinking about (modifying) action in the
light of conceptual knowledge. Schön uses "reflection" for both.
Some of the main sub-dimensions of this "what" dimension are:
- Actions / concepts / facts / perceptions
- Public, shared knowledge / personal experience
- Category or instance. [?described/desired behaviour]
- What is it related to or checked
against? This question is particularly neglected in many treatments. This
in turn may be because the Kolb diagram of reflection depicts only a cycle,
and omits the other input(s) that must be there for any act of (type A)
reflection. If we took the diagram literally, reflection would mean only the
sterile internal rehearsal of the original material, rather than new
processing by relating it for the first time to other internal material.
That neglect probably is the cause of Colin Holroyd's unease with a tendency
to deny the role of fixed, pre-existing, shared knowledge as still
important. It also quickly leads you to recognising that there are a large
(and open-ended) number of different kinds of reflection, depending on which
connections you examine (e.g. check action against theory, against what other
theories you know, against what others do i.e. standard practice, ....).
Again, the same subdimensions apply, and all combinations can occur e.g.
checking a new concept against old private experience, using a new experience
to revisit an old (understanding of) a public theory.
- When is the reflection done?
The first form of this question is posed in relation to action
events. This is the distinction between reflection for / in / on
(depending on whether the thinking is before / during or / after the action
being thought about). This distinction expands Schön's in/on distinction,
and was made by John Cowan, and is also made on
Ray McAleese's home page
which has pointers to further material.
Note however that this does not really cover the important issue of
new/old material. For much reflection, one can ask what is the new material
that is prompting reflection, as opposed to older material against which it is
being processed. Thus reflection-on is largely about taking new observations of
actual effects of action and comparing them to the intended effect, while
reflection-for is largely about taking a new plan just hypothesised in the
mind, and checking it against relevant knowledge (perhaps to catch what Norman
calls "mistakes" as opposed to "slips" — plans inconsistent with the actor's
knowledge because there was an error in their generation as opposed to
execution). But reflection, especially of type A, may be using much older
material, sometimes comparing old with very old, as well as comparing a new
concept against older ones. Both Galileo and Einstein made important advances
in physics by thought experiments: which are reflective exercises that point
out to other scientists that there is a conclusion to be drawn simply from
reflection upon known material without new data at all.
Thus this "when" dimension could be recast away from the special question of
when in relation to action (which in any case does not apply to all reflection)
and towards which, if either, of the two items being related is the new one:
which gives three cases to cross with the other dimensions.
- What for.
In addition is John Cowan's distinction between
analytic vs. evaluative reflection.
This concerns the regulation of action (without explicit concern with
concepts or theories), and so is more strongly related to the type B
conception of reflection as to do with self-regulation and understanding
through thought. Analytic reflection refers to analysing an action in its
own terms, for instance noticing what you did and why, and against all your
relevant predictive knowledge (important because circumstances modify most
plans, even if you had one, because people sometimes make mistakes in
generating even quite ordinary plans, and because many plans are hypotheses
to be checked against possible constraints and conflicts).
Evaluative reflection refers to comparing what you did and its effect with
some standard of what you would wish to have achieved. To do this properly
(he suggests), you must describe both the aspiration (standard) and the
actual performance separately, and then describe the difference.
Analytic reflection is formative, to develop abilities; while evaluative is
summative, "for deeper and more purposive learning" i.e. to develop the goals
and standards you set yourself (not just your skill at achieving whatever you
attempt), and again John's claim is that this has a positive effect on learning.
For analytic reflection, the new item is the plan of action or
possibly observation of behaviour (but not effects), and the old material will
be predictive knowledge and any consideration of constraints and aims that an
action should conform to. For evaluative reflection, the new item is the
effects of action, and the old material likely to be the desired effects.
A comparable distinction occurs in Norman's (1986) "theory of action" and its
two sides, with action overall being conceived of as comprising first the
generation of behaviour, and then perception (as an instrinsic part of action)
that is used to observe and evaluate the effects against the desired goal(s).
Note that the first two questions or dimensions are associated with type A
reflection, the third may be conceived generally or only in relation to
action, and the last only applies to actions and is associated
with type B reflection.
All of this applies to learners learning about some domain or topic; but it
also applies to teachers and all professionals learning while doing their job.
So in a teaching and learning situation, there is reflection for and by
learners, but also the reflection teachers may do about their own performance
(rather than about the subject matter itself).
Particularly important classes of object for II.1 and II.2
There are some kinds of connection or relationship that are thought (by
various theorists) to be particularly important for learners to make, and so
for teachers to support thinking (reflection) about.
- Public concepts vs. personal experience. Linking the concepts in
textbooks (abstract, with technical vocabulary) to personal experiences,
including sensori-motor ones.
In Laurillard's model this is the relationship between
the top and bottom parts of her model. In the education literature this is
closely related to the standard horror of producing students who can pass
exams on the concepts but do not notice the application of those concepts to
things in their own experience, in the world around them, or even in the lab
exercises they completed.
- Iteration especially within each of those two levels (public concept and
personal experience) separately. Within the personal level, such iteration is
what Schön focussed on, stressing that an important kind of reflection
("experiential learning") does not require links to abstract concepts.
Within the conceptual level, such reflection might focus on considering links
with other kinds of concept, even across traditional discipline boundaries.
This is the Kolb cycle idea, and in the
Laurillard model is represented as the loops between activities, and the
repetition of some of them. It is to do with alternating between action of
some kind, and thinking about the action and observations of its effects.
- Another general class is to link the general and the particular, the
abstract with specific instances. For concepts, that means linking with
examples; for actions, that means linking plans with action in specific cases.
The linguistic method: search for examples, counterexamples, and rules that
apply to them.
Reflection must be a near relative both of critical thinking, and of deep (in
contrast to shallow) learning. In fact, we can probably equate reflection with
critical thinking turned on one's own ideas and actions as opposed to those
presented by others. Reflection is more often used to refer to actions, and
critical thinking more often to alternative theories of the same phenomena, but
the framework above applies equally to both.
Similarly, there is a very close connection with understanding and deep
learning. First of all, recall that deep learners are characterised by
aiming not at learning but at understanding (Marton et al.; 1984).
Then we must recognise that, in spite of everyday language usage, there is no
identifiable completion or end of understanding or deep learning. In
everyday chat we may say "yes, I understand", but most serious academics know
they continue to pick up new, interesting aspects or consequences of a
concept indefinitely (often from their students): aspects they hadn't
apprehended before. This is easy to understand in the framework above: there
is no definite end to the number of things you might relate a given concept
to: complete understanding would mean you had explicitly related it to every
other datum and concept in the universe.
Another way of listing types of depth and understanding is
given here.
The Laurillard model to a great extent embodies or includes the Kolb /
Schön model of reflection as a part. One of its three underlying
principles and symmetries is the distinction between the level of public
conceptions and that of personal experience; reflection is seen as the
traffic between the two (in fully developed learning processes), where the
learner compares, relates the two levels and makes modifications to improve
each in the light of the other. Laurillard has 4 of her 12 activities
concerned with this, one of which is actually named "reflection". A
criticism of her model in the light of the fuller range of "reflection"
suggested above would be that her model has no explicit place for reflection
(connections) of other kinds, for instance considering the relationship of a
new concept with old ones from other topics.
Note the difference between connecting (relating) an item to a) other
conceptual items e.g. what was learned last term; b) personal experience,
perceptions, etc. And the difference between linking a new concept back to
existing knowledge; vs. linking forward by planning actions. I.e. there is
the problem that in general it may not just be the new concept and old personal
experience that needs to be linked.
The real issue in reflection in general is thinking over something,
checking for new associations and inferences, without having any particular
goal in mind: i.e. a goal of understanding, not doing or learning. But the
issue here is connecting the two levels of public conceptions vs. personal
experience.
Many (most?) people I discuss the Laurillard model with find the
adaptation/reflection issues the hardest to see how to address (i.e. to
support by explicit teaching actions). E.g. how could
you possibly support them by computer? Also, I'm told that young children
can't do it at all: this is something only adults can do; and the ability to
reflect is a truly developmental one that emerges. Hence
Tolmie (personal communication) argued that
these 4 activities are qualitatively different from the others. The others are
externally visible activities e.g. with material products. Adaptation is too:
using concepts to change your procedure, which is then observable. Basically
both are observable with one extra step i.e. re-doing one of the first 8
activities.
A first pass is, that prediction tasks force adaptation, explanation
tasks force reflection. Pre-lab activities (such as those developed by Alex
Johnstone and others) are directly adaptation tasks
(theory to practice). Diagnoses of problems in practicals are directly
reflection tasks.
I shall argue that reflection is not worth special attention or emphasis,
not because it is unimportant but because, like breathing, although essential
for learning it goes without saying. The limiting factors are elsewhere.
Because of the vagueness of the term "reflection" (i.e. the inconsistency of
its usage) the point needs to be made for each major meaning.
I shall therefore discuss separately reflection by teachers and reflection by
learners; and consider for each three meanings: thinking, iteration, and
relating the two levels of public concepts and personal experience.
The base (dictionary) meaning of reflection is thinking. Yes thinking is
important, but doesn't that go without saying?
A deeper idea is that of an iterative cycle, as discussed by Kolb and
Schön. The idea of learning and developing by acting, extracting
lessons from the experience, and so improving one's capability for that kind
of action.
Yes, that is a profoundly important and general concept. It is also old. It
is the key idea in cybernetics (and the influence of that on what is now
cognitive science many decades ago): the idea of applying the concept of
a feedback loop from control engineering to human behaviour.
It is the idea in the TOTE cycle (Miller et al. 1960).
It is the idea in Don Norman's Theory of Action (Norman, 1986).
And it is represented in the Laurillard model by the iterative groups of
activities and loopbacks between them e.g. activities 1-4 (instead of just 1
and 2) etc.
In other words, we haven't waited for the notion of reflection to hear about
the need for such cycles, which are much wider significance. In fact, they
seem basic to all action, as well as all learning.
On the other hand, in my experience of teachers, they haven't needed to be
told to reflect in order to notice problems with their activities and to
consider changes: neither thinking nor expecting a cycle seems a problem.
Instead I have seen two different problems or effects.
The first is in reporting back to teachers with an evaluation report on some
piece of their teaching. Typically they don't need suggestions or even
interpretations, but seize on the data and immediately think of changes they
will try out. This suggests that a bottleneck was getting good feedback from
students about the activity. Thus techniques like ones John
Cowan mentioned are the key (e.g. starting a lesson by asking them to write
down what they most want to learn in the next hour; ending by asking them to
write down the most important thing they learned, and the most important
thing they still haven't learned). Most teachers I know will react to this
information without any urging to "reflect!", but they don't normally get
such information. Providing it is what makes the difference.
The other observation, this time backed by the literature on the
ineffectiveness of standard course feedback questionnaires in stimulating
change, is that besides useful data, teachers sometimes need new ideas about
what changes they could make: ideas about alternative practices. This too is
not supplied by reflection, but by having contact with good ideas about
teaching, usually from other people.
The last observation suggests again, not that teachers need to be urged to do
this kind of thinking, but that the bottleneck, at least in HE, is usually
having access to relevant abstract conceptions about teaching.
Again, who could dispute that thinking is good for learning? Indeed, although
some practices (e.g. lectures) may tend to suppress thinking by learners, many
others are, and have always been, specifically designed to provide it:
exercises, essays, etc.
Who could need reminding of its importance? Advocating iteration between
action and reflecting on its results amounts to advocating giving students
feedback on their exercises. Iteration in general is an underlying principle
in the Laurillard model represented by the "to and fro" between left and
right sides of the diagram, and by having four rather than two activities in
both top and bottom halves of it.
As discussed earlier, this is important and a feature of the Laurillard model.
It is also only one special case of all the kinds of thinking and relating that
are desirable.
In all cases, the real bottleneck for learners seems to be time for
reflective thinking, not being urged to do so. Certainly that has been true
for me from the age of 16, when I finished doing a physics course in a slow
stream for those supposed not to be interested, but which thus left me time
really to think about each topic in depth. After that, rushing greatly
reduced how much I could think through and therefore understand what I was
taught, until my PhD.
Learners can't think because teachers put them under endless pressure to meet
deadlines and push on to the next topic. And the same is seen everywhere.
One of the very irritating things about (British) TV is the way interviewers
constantly either interrupt or put the next question within a split second of
the last reply. They never ever stop to think about the answer, nor allow
their audience to do so. This continual demonstration of disinterest in what
is said is rude, and prevents understanding, thought, and reflection.
Similarly as a teacher, what I probably need most to be continually reminded
to do is to allow silences for thought. Calling this "reflection" is fine,
although "thought" is plainer English.
It is far from clear (to me) that reflection is worth much prominence in
either theories of the learning and teaching process, or in our teaching
practice. I feel it is a secondary not primary issue.
This impulse to be dismissive has these (not necessarily mutually
consistent) components:
- I find there are many senses of "reflection", and most who use it don't
seem to have reflected on this. If new practice is worth developing there
should be a clear theoretical position behind it; and if there is a clear
theoretical position then at the very least clear definitions and discussions
of how this is and is not consistent with other usages should be available.
This is not the case, as I hope the above makes clear.
- This unclarity means among other things that perhaps we all do it anyway,
like the man who was astonished to discover that he had been speaking prose
all his life; in which case most of us need pay no new attention to it.
After all, "reflection" just means "thinking", and I'm sure we all agree that
thinking is helpful to learning.
- The same issue occurs in other theories (such as the theory of action:
Norman, 1986). And there, it is conceived of as an inherent part of action
(like breathing), not some new discovery to be promoted by special approaches
because otherwise ordinary learners and practitioners will omit it.
- It is already an assimilated (unemphasised) component of the more
interesting theories in education, such as Laurillard's and the work on deep
and shallow learning. Making a fuss about reflection is to focus on one
component and ignore the overall picture.
- Similarly for practice: reflection is a part of or effect of good practice,
and there is no obvious need to focus on it more than, or separately from,
others. It will occur without special attention. For instance, if the
Laurillard model is applied systematically to the design of teaching provision,
reflection will have its place, just as exposition will.
- As for promoting reflection for learners, which is reflection in the sense
of thinking about oneself, we should remember that shallow learning is
characterised by striving to learn: perhaps promoting learning diaries etc.
will erode deep learning and promote shallow learning. (Understanding diaries,
i.e. diaries recording understandings sought and achieved,
are what that work would predict are required.)
- In considering reflection for teaching practitioners, if your aim,
like mine, is to improve the quality of L&T in HE, then in my experience
it is not reflection that is usually the bottleneck. Instead, one bottleneck
is getting useful feedback on my teaching: so techniques like ones John
Cowan mentioned are the key (e.g. starting a lesson by asking them to write
down what they most want to learn in the next hour; ending by asking them to
write down the most important thing they learned, and the most important
thing they still haven't learned). Most teachers I know will react to this
information without any urging to "reflect!", but they don't normally get
such information. Providing it is what makes the difference. The other
important bottleneck is having ideas about what new practices to try, given
information on problems in L&T. This too is not supplied by reflection,
but by having contact with good ideas about teaching, usually from other
people.
So: Reflection is a secondary issue, like vitamin B. We all need vitamin B,
but it is only one subset among a large set of necessary elements. It is not
important like the general concept of vitamins. And when you analyse it, you
find there are many different micronutrients all separately essential: but
some were originally confounded as one "vitamin B", others as vitamin A, C, D
etc.; and still others such as iron, iodine, zinc not called vitamins at all.
But, against all that, is the witness of some enthusiasts who say it benefits
them personally. And that experiential evidence could be worth more than all
this analysis.
Find and cite the Harré book: see References section below.
Another comment
When I came across McCabe & Tobias Thejll-Madsen's website on reflection
it prompted me to revisit my existing ideas on the term and concepts of
reflection.
Gavin
McCabe & Tobias Thejll-Madsen's website on reflection
(https://www.ed.ac.uk/reflection)
Their definition of (critical) reflection is:
"The conscious examination of past experiences, thoughts, and ways of doing
things. Its goal is to surface learning about oneself and the situation, and
to bring meaning to it in order to inform the present and the future. It
challenges the status quo of practice, thoughts, and assumptions and may
therefore inform our decisions, actions, attitudes, beliefs, and understanding
about ourselves."
My own views are above on this web page, especially in the section
"Why reflection isn't worth focussing on".
One thing to consider is that there is no agreement, in the literature on
reflection as a whole, about the terms used.
McCabe & Thejll-Madsen seem only to consider the value of training
learners to deliberately analyse their own conscious goals. On the one hand,
they, and some others, think this is valuable and that is good to know.
I have myself admired, and second-marked, exam scripts by psychology students
which included such exercises and it was clear to me that many of the students
found this kind of reflection personally valuable.
On the other hand a wider view of education, and investigating a wider range
of the education literature, contains many other important senses of
"reflection". A simple demonstration of this is to use Google Scholar, and
type in "reflection" as the sole search term. The first hit is an article by
Boud, and clearly belongs in the McCabe & Thejll-Madsen sense of the word.
However the second article returned is a chapter in a book entitled
"Psycho-analytic explorations", and is clearly not the same sense. The seventh
match returned is a journal paper titled "There's no such thing as
reflection". Further examples I found in the literature (prompted by Sfard --
see below) are:
- "Reflection, Communication, and Learning Mathematics,"
Wistedt (1994) in Learning and Instruction
- "Democratic Competence and Reflective Knowing in mathematics"
Skovsmose, O. (1992). For the learning of mathematics 12(2), 2-11.
- "Reflective Discourse and Collective Reflection," Cobb et al. (1997)
Journal for research in mathematics education, 28(3), 258-277.
It is clear that McCabe & Thejll-Madsen have not done a
systematic review, and are ignoring other kinds of reflection within the
academic literature.
And in my own opinion, these other kinds are more important.
Further comments on the limitations of their work, and of other
interesting things in education which you might like to learn about
Another demonstration of the many important meanings of reflection is this:
Here is a different list of terms, all meaning much the same thing,
could be:
- Meditation
- Contemplation
- The examined life ("an unexamined life is not worth living"
-- Plato's Apology, attributed to Socrates).
- Prayer (Sister Wendy Beckett, a devoted nun but also an Oxford graduate,
and an exceptionally gifted school teacher, as revealed in a BBC series of
talks on Art History). I would call "reflection" what she called prayer:
thinking about what God really wanted or meant. She had to teach because she
had to bring in her share of income to her convent, because it didn't have a
large inherited endowment. But what she would like to have spent all her time
doing was prayer (i.e. in my terms, thinking, reflecting).
- Thinking.
- Deep learning. That is what I myself would call it.
But for me, deep learning is working to add new types of link to a given new
atom of knowledge.
But there may be an unlimited number of different types of "depth", because
the number of types of link,
all useful in one or another context, is unlimited.
My own critique of the limited focus on rational self-examination as important
is that it subconsciously presupposes that learning is a rational process, and
we should have a goal, work out a plan for how to achieve it, and then execute
this line of thinking. My interest in education -- in learning and teaching
-- has forced me to abandon this. It has some truth in HE: in universities on
the whole learners know their overall goals (e.g. to learn physics, to get a
medical degree and have eventually an affluent lifestyle because medicine is
becoming more not less important in the world today. But this is by no means a
simple truth.
Firstly, experiments called "Dr. Fox experiments" demonstrated
that ordinary US undergraduates were about equally motivated by wanting good
marks and by being interested in a lecture itself.
(This field of experiments was reviewed in:
Marsh, H.W. (1987) "Students' evaluations of university teaching: research
findings, methodological issues, and directions for future research"
Int. journal of educational research vol.11 no.3 pp.253-388.
doi: 10.1016/0883-0355(87)90001-2
[A section only of this huge paper is on Dr. Fox type experiments])
This undermines the view that (at least in HE) learning is a rational
goal-directed process. Instead most students show they are influenced by two
separate kinds of goal, rather than having only one aim and focussing only on
that.
Secondly, a much more subtle argument by Sfard exists. Her paper is a
profound joy to read and is one of my personal choices for the five best papers
on education I have ever read:
Sfard,A. (1998)
"On Two Metaphors for Learning and the Dangers of Choosing Just One"
Educational Researcher Vol.27 No.2 pp.4-13
doi: 10.3102/0013189X027002004
The two metaphors are: the acquisition metaphor and the participation metaphor.
The former is about how we so often tend to think of knowledge as an object we
can acquire and possess; while participation focusses on how at other times
knowledge shows itself in how you can interact with other people.
Both are true, but there is no way to reduce one to the other.
Thirdly, consider a brilliant title for a brilliant paper which brings out
counterintuitive observations.
Peter Elbow's (1987) memorably titled paper on this point: "Closing my
eyes as I speak: An argument for ignoring the audience" which begins with the
quotation "Very often people don't listen to you when you speak to them. It's
only when you talk to yourself that they prick up their ears." This of course
is the opposite of lesson number one in most writing classes: consider the
audience.
Peter Elbow (1987) "Closing my eyes as I speak: An argument for
ignoring the audience" College English vol.49 no.1 pp.50-69
How can we understand this? At the least, it goes against a simple top down
rational theory of what works in education. Reflection is about struggling to
understand, how it is hard, how it is often invaluable; and how when someone
shows that struggle we all subconsciously know this is a far more important bit
of the session than the rest.
It also implies that struggle is part of learning -- and usually, the good
part. (Some would say, it is another way of describing what is involved in
Piaget's distinction between assimilation (adding another example of
something we understand already) and accommodation (creating a new schema or
at least modifying an abstract concept like a category).
This further implies that we are only learning in an important way when we are
reprocessing, rather than accepting passively, material.
And "reflection" is generally a term for reprocessing mental contents;
but there are many ways and types of doing this.
It is clear that McCabe & Thejll-Madsen have not done a systematic
literature review of reflection, and are ignoring other kinds of reflection
within the academic literature. And in my own opinion, these other kinds are
more important.
"Reflection" is generally a term for reprocessing and/or extending mental
contents; but there are many ways and types of doing this. For undergraduates
at least two types are important, but often confused (at least at first).
These are:
Boud,D., Keogh,R. & Walker,D. (1985) (eds.)
Reflection: turning experience into learning (Kogan Page)
Boud,D., Cohen,R. & Walker,D. (1993) (eds.)
Using experience for learning (Open University Press)
Dewey,J.(1933) How we think (New York: Heath)
Dewey,J.(1938) Experience and education
Harré, Rom (1993) Social Being
Revised edition. (Oxford: Blackwell)
Or maybe it's in a book on his philosophy of science?
Kolb, D.A. (1984) Experiential learning
Prentice-Hall Inc, Englewood Cliffs, NJ, USA
[not checked] Kolb D A (1976) The Learning Style Inventory : Technical
Manual McBer & Co, Boston
Kolb, D.A. & Fry,R. (1975) "Towards an applied theory of experiential
learning" ch.3 pp.33-57 in Cooper,C.L. (Ed.) Theories of Group
Processes, (Wiley: London)
Laurillard, D. (1993) Rethinking university teaching: A framework
for the effective use of educational technology (Routledge: London).
See also
an online diagram of her model
Marton,F., D.Hounsell & N.Entwistle (1984) (eds.) The experience of
learning (Edinburgh: Scottish academic press)
Miller G.A., Galanter E., & Pribram K. (1960) Plans and the
structure of behavior (New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston).
Norman D.A. (1986) "Cognitive Engineering" in D.A.Norman & S.W.Draper
(eds.) ch.3 pp.31-61 User Centered System Design
(Erlbaum: London).
Perry, W.G. (1968/70) Forms of intellectual and ethical development in the
college years (New York: Holt, Rhinehart and Winston)
Rorty, R. (1980) Philosophy and the mirror of nature
(Blackwell: Oxford).
Schön, D.A. (1983) The reflective practitioner: How professionals
think in action (Temple Smith: London) (Basic books?)
Schön,D.A. (1987) Educating the reflective practitioner
Schön,D.A. (1991) (ed.)
The reflective turn: case studies in and on educational practice
Suchman, L.A. (1987) Plans and situated actions: the problem of
human-machine communication (Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK)